Value-free paradise is lost. Economists could learn from artists
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.18778/1899-2226.23.4.01Keywords:
philosophy of science, methodology of economics, value-free economics, Max WeberAbstract
Despite the conclusions from the contemporary philosophy of science, many economists cherish the ideal of positive science. Therefore, value-free economics is still the central paradigm in economics. The first aim of the paper is to investigate economics’ axiomatic assumptions from an epistemological perspective. The critical analysis of the literature shows that the positive-normative dichotomy is exaggerated. Moreover, value-free economics is based on normative foundations that have a negative impact on individuals and society. The paper’s second aim is to show that economics’ normativity is not a problem because the discussion concerning values is possible and unavoidable. In this context, Weber and other methodologists are investigated. The conclusion of the paper is that science can thrive without strict methodological rules thanks to institutional mechanisms. Therefore, economists could learn from artists who accept the world without absolute rules. This perspective opens the possibility for methodological pluralism and normative approaches.
References
Ainslie, G. (1975). Specious reward: A behavioral theory of impulsiveness and impulse control. Psychological Bulletin, 82(4), 463–496. https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/h0076860
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1037/h0076860
Akerlof, G. (2020). Sins of Omission and the Practice of Economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 58(2), 405–418.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1257/jel.20191573
Angner, E. (2019). We’re all behavioral economists now. Journal of Economic Methodology, 26(3), 195–207.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2019.1625210
Backhouse, R. E. & Cherrier, B. (2017). The age of the applied economist: the transformation of economics since the 1970s. History of Political Economy, 49, 1–33.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1215/00182702-4166239
Barnes, J. (Ed.). (1984). The complete works of Aristotle Vol. 2. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar
Becker, G. S. (1976). The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226217062.001.0001
Berg, N., & Gigerenzer, G. (2010). As-if behavioral economics: Neoclassical economics in disguise? History of Economic Ideas, 18(1), 133–165.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1677168
Blaug, M. (1992). The Methodology of Economics: Or How Economists Explain (2nd ed). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511528224
Blaug, M. (1997). Ugly Currents in Modern Economics. Options Politiques, 18(17), 3–8.
Google Scholar
Boland, L. A. (1979). A critique of Friedman’s critics. Journal of Economic Literature, 17(2), 503–522.
Google Scholar
Boldyrev, I. & Svetlova, E. (Eds.) (2016). Enacting Dismal Science: New Perspectives on the Performativity of Economics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-48876-3
Brickman, P., Coates, D. & Janoff-Bulman, R. (1978). Lottery winner and accident victims: is happiness relative? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36(8), 917–927. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.36.8.917
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.36.8.917
Brzeziński, M., Gorynia, M. & Hockuba, Z. (2008). Ekonomia a inne nauki społeczne na początku XXI w. Między imperializmem a kooperacją. Ekonomista, 2, 201–232.
Google Scholar
Caldwell, B. J. (1992). A Critique of Friedman’s Methodological Instrumentalism: A Modification. Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology, 10, 119–128.
Google Scholar
Callon, M. (2006). What does it mean to say that economics is performative? CSI Working Papers Series, no. 005, Centre de Sociologie de l’Innovation (CSI), Mines ParisTech.
Google Scholar
Cedrini, M. & Fontana, M. (2018). Just another niche in the wall? How specialization is changing the face of mainstream economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 42(2), 427–451. https://doi.org/10.1093/cje/bex003
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/cje/bex003
Colander, D. (2000). The death of neoclassical economics. Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 22(2), 127–143. https://doi.org/10.1080/104277100 50025330
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/10427710050025330
Colander, D., Holt, R. & Rosser, J. (2004). The Changing Face of Mainstream Economics. Review of Political Economy, 16(4), 485–499. https://doi.org/10.1080/0953825042000256702
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/0953825042000256702
Davis, J. B. (2006). The Turn in Economics: Neoclassical Dominance to Mainstream Pluralism. Journal of Institutional Economics, 2(1), 1–20. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1744137405000263
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1744137405000263
Dow, S. C. (2012). Foundations for new economic thinking: A collection of essays. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137000729
Dun, F. Van (1986). Economics and the Limits of Value-Free Science. Reason Papers, 11, 17–32.
Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. (1993). Against method (3rd ed). New York–London: Verso.
Google Scholar
Fiedor, B. & Ostapiuk, A. (2017). Utylitaryzm versus aksjologiczne i społeczne uwarunkowania wyborów ekonomicznych. In: E. Mączyńska, & J. Sójka (Eds.), Etyka i ekonomia. W stronę nowego paradygmatu (pp. 19–44). Warszawa: Polskie Towarzystwo Ekonomiczne.
Google Scholar
Fourcade, M., Ollion, E. & Algan, Y. (2015). The superiority of economists. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 29(1), 89–114.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1257/jep.29.1.89
Friedman, M. (1953). Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Google Scholar
Graupe, S. (2019). “Waging the war of ideas”: Economics as a textbook science and its possible influence on human minds. In: S. Decker, W. Elsner & S. Flechtner (Eds.), Advancing pluralism in teaching economics (pp. 173–191). London: Routledge.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315177809-12
Hands, D. W. (2001). Reflection Without Rules: Economic Methodology and Contemporary Science Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511612602
Hands, D. W. (2007). Effective tension in Robbins’s economic methodology. In: F. Cowell and A. Witztum (Eds.), Lionel Robbins’ essay on the nature and significance of economic science. 75th anniversary conference proceedings (pp. 152–168). London: London School of Economics and Political Science.
Google Scholar
Hands, D. W. (2012). The positive-normative dichotomy and economics. In: U. Mäki (Ed.), Philosophy of economics (pp. 219–239). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-444-51676-3.50009-9
Hardt, Ł. (2020). Utylitaryzm, deontologia i etyka cnót: zbieżne czy przeciwstawne fundamenty etyczne ekonomii? Ekonomista, 2, 249–265.
Google Scholar
Hausman, D. M. (1992). The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511752032
Hausman, D. M. (1998). Problems with realism in economics. Economics & Philosophy, 14(2), 185–213. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267100003837
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267100003837
Hausman, D. M. & McPherson, M. S. (2006). Economic Analysis, Moral Philosophy and Public Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511754289
Hempel, C. G. (1945). Studies in the Logic of Confirmation (I.). Mind, 54(213), 1–26.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/LIV.213.1
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2017). Revisiting Friedman’s F53. Popper, Knight, and Weber. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/12910/1/Friedmans%20F53.pdf
Google Scholar
Hutchison, T. W. (1981). The Politics and Philosophy of Economics. New York: New York University Press.
Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263–292. https://doi.org/10.2307/1914185
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/1914185
Keynes, J. N. (1999). The scope and method of political economy. Kitchener, Ontario: Batoche Books.
Google Scholar
Klamer, A., McCloskey, D. N. & Solow, R. M. (Eds.). (1988). The consequences of economic rhetoric. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511759284
Klappholz, K. (1964). Value Judgments and Economics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15(58), 97–114.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/XV.58.97
Klimczak, B. (2014). Aksjologiczne uwikłanie ekonomii. Annales. Etyka w Życiu Gospodarczym, 17(1), 9–21.
Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice. In: T. S. Kuhn, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1996). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (3rd ed). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226458106.001.0001
Lakatos, I. (1980). The methodology of scientific research programmes. Philosophical Papers, Volume 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
Lawson, T. (2015). Essays on: The Nature and State of Modern Economics. Abingdon: Routledge.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315724416
Lazear, E. P. (2000). Economic imperialism. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115(1), 99–146. https://doi.org/10.1162/003355300554683
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1162/003355300554683
Madra, Y. M. (2016). Late Neoclassical Economics: The restoration of theoretical humanism in contemporary economic theory. New York: Routledge.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315817255
Mäki, U. (1995). Diagnosing McCloskey. Journal of Economic Literature, 33(3), 1300–1318.
Google Scholar
Mäki, U. (2009). Unrealistic assumptions and unnecessary confusions: Rereading and rewriting F53 as a realist statement. In: U. Mäki (Ed.), The methodology of positive economics. Reflections on the Milton Friedman legacy (pp. 90–116). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511581427.005
Mäki, U. (2012). Realism and antirealism about economics. In: U. Mäki (Ed.), Philosophy of economics (pp. 3–24). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-444-51676-3.50001-4
McCloskey, D. N. (1983). The rhetoric of economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 21(2), 481–517.
Google Scholar
McCloskey, D. N. (1994). Knowledge and Persuasion in Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511599347
Megill, A. (1985). Prophets of Extremity: Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault, Derrida. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1525/9780520908376
Merton, R. K. (1942). A note on science and democracy. Journal of Legal and Political Sociology, 1, 115–126.
Google Scholar
Miller, D. (1974). Popper’s Qualitative Theory of Verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25(2), 166–177.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/25.2.166
Mirowski, P. (2002). Machine dreams: Economics becomes a cyborg science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511613364
Mongin, P. (2001). Value Judgments and Value Neutrality in Economics: A Perspective from Today. https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.200.2887&rep=rep1&type=pdf
Google Scholar
Morgan, M. (2012). The world in the model: How economists work and think. Cambridge–New York: Cambridge University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139026185
Myrdal, G. (1970). Objectivity in Social Research. London: Gerald Duckworth.
Google Scholar
Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science. Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F. (1954). On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense. In: W. Kaufmann (Ed. & Transl.), The Portable Nietzsche. New York: Penguin Books.
Google Scholar
Ostapiuk, A. (2017). Matematyzacja ekonomii – grzech pierworodny? Wieloaspektowa analiza wpływu i przyczyn. Ekonomia XXI wieku, 13(1), 91–104.
Google Scholar
Ostapiuk, A. (2019a). Droga ekonomii wolnej od wartościowania do epistemologicznej pychy. Użycie i nadużycie matematyki przez ekonomistów. Zagadnienia Filozoficzne w Nauce, 67, 153–202.
Google Scholar
Ostapiuk, A. (2019b). Human Now versus Human over Time. When Instrumental Rationality and Utility Are Not Enough. Panoeconomicus, 66(5), 633–657.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2298/PAN161203026O
Ostapiuk, A. (2020). The Eclipse of Value-Free Economics. The concept of multiple self versus homo economicus. Wrocław: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu Ekonomicznego we Wrocławiu.
Google Scholar
Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature: The decline of violence in history and its causes. New York: Penguin Group.
Google Scholar
Poincaré, H. (2010). Science and method (F. Maitland, transl.). New York: Cosimo Classics.
Google Scholar
Polanyi, M. (1958). Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Basic Books.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1063/1.3060577
Putnam, H. (2002). The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1951). Main trends in recent philosophy: Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60(1), 20–43.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2181906
Ratajczak, M. (2014). Ekonomia i edukacja ekonomiczna w dobie finansyzacji gospodarki. Ekonomista, 2, 207–219.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.14746/rpeis.2014.76.2.19
Reiss, J. (2013). Philosophy of economics: A contemporary introduction. Abingdon: Routledge.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203559062
Reiss, J. (2017). Fact-value entanglement in positive economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 24(2), 134–149. https://doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2017.1309749
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/1350178X.2017.1309749
Robbins, L. (1932). An essay on the nature & significance of economic science. London: Macmillan.
Google Scholar
Rodrik, D. (2015). Economics rules: The rights and wrongs of the dismal science. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.17323/1726-3247-2015-4-39-59
Samuelson, P. (1952). Economic Theory and Mathematics – an Appraisal. American Economic Review, 42(2), 56–66.
Google Scholar
Schweitzer, A. (1970). Typological Method in Economics: Max Weber’s Contribution. History of Political Economy, 2(1), 66–96.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1215/00182702-2-1-66
Sen, A. K. (1970). Collective Choices and Social Welfare. Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd.
Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. (1987). On Ethics & Economics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Google Scholar
Sen, A. K. (1993). Internal Consistency of Choice. Econometrica, 61(3), 495–521.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2951715
Thaler, R. H. (1980). Toward a Positive Theory of Consumer Choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1(1), 39–60. https://doi.org/10.1016/0167-2681(80)90051-7
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/0167-2681(80)90051-7
Thaler, R. H. (2015). Misbehaving: The Making of Behavioral Economics. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Google Scholar
Thaler, R. H. (2016). Behavioral economics: Past, present, and future. American Economic Review, 106(7), 1577–1600.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1257/aer.106.7.1577
Weber, M. (1949). The methodology of the social sciences (E. Shils & H. Finch, transl.). Glencoe: The Free Press.
Google Scholar
Weintraub, E. R. (2002). How economics became a mathematical science. Durham–London: Duke University Press.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv125jtwm
Witztum, A. (2007). Ethics and the science of economics: Robbins’s enduring fallacy. In: F. Cowell and A. Witztum (Eds.), Lionel Robbins’ essay on the nature and significance of economic science. 75th anniversary conference proceedings (pp. 57–85). London: School of Economics and Political Science.
Google Scholar
Wolin, S. S. (1981). Max Weber: Legitimation, Method, and the Politics of Theory. Political Theory, 9(3), 401–424.
Google Scholar
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/009059178100900308
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.