The progress of civilization and the de dicto/de re distinction

Authors

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.54.02

Keywords:

de dicto belief, de re belief, transcendental arguments, argument from understanding language, argument from progress of civilization

Abstract

In this paper I present my own argument in support of the thesis that de dicto beliefs are, in at least one sense, more basic than de re beliefs. This argument rests on the fact of the progress of civilization, which appears, as I try to demonstrate, not to be possible without de dicto beliefs constituting a key part of the mental processes of the inventor. My argument is to counterweigh the force of Tyler Burge’s argument for the fundamentality of de re beliefs, leading to the conclusion that beliefs de re are a necessary condition of language understanding and having propositional attitudes at all (Burge 1977, p. 347-348). The first part of the paper is devoted to the examination of the structure of different versions of transcendental arguments – objective and subjective, the second part focuses on an analysis of Burge’s argument from language understanding, while the aim of the third part is to present the Reader with the argument from the progress of civilization. The exposition of the argument is followed by a discussion of certain possible objections which the argument may face. 

References

Burge T. (1977). Belief de re. The Journal of Philosophy, 74 (6), 338-362
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2025871

Cresswell M. J., Hughes E. (1968). An Introduction to Modal Logic. London: Methuen and CoKaplan D. (1968). Quantifying in. Synthese 19, 178-214
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00568057

Putnam H. (1999). Brains in a Vat. In: K. DeRose, T. A. Warfield (eds.), Skepticism. A Contemporary Reader (27-42). New-York Oxford: Oxford University Press
View in Google Scholar

Quine W. V. (1956). Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 53, 177-187
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2022451

Richard M. (1997). Propositional Attitudes. In: B. Hale, C. Wright (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language (197-226). Blackwell Publishers
View in Google Scholar

Searle J. R. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3 (3), 417-457
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00005756

Stern R. (2008). Kant’s Response to Skepticism. In: J. Greco (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism (265-279). Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195183214.003.0013

Stern R. (2011). Transcendental Arguments. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Summer 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/transcendental-arguments/
View in Google Scholar

Strawson P. (1966). Objectivity and Unity. In: The Bounds of Sense (72-117). London: Methuen & Co Ltd
View in Google Scholar

Strawson P. (1985). Scepticism and Naturalism: some Varieties. New York: Columbia University Press
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7312/stra92820

Vahid H. (2011), Skepticism and Varieties of Transcendental Arguments. Logos & Episteme, 2 (3), 395-411
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/logos-episteme20112321

Warfield T. A. (1999). A Priori Knowledge of the World: Knowing the World by Knowing Our Minds. In: K. DeRose, T. A. Warfield (eds.), Skepticism. A Contemporary Reader (76-90). Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press
View in Google Scholar

Downloads

Published

2021-12-30

How to Cite

Ebner, M. (2021). The progress of civilization and the de dicto/de re distinction. Hybris, 54(3), 32–49. https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.54.02

Issue

Section

Articles