Kripkenstein from the mathematical point of view: a preliminary survey

Authors

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.34.10

Keywords:

Kripke, philosophy of mathematics, non-factualism, Platonism

Abstract

This paper deals with the problem of the impact of Kripke’s skeptical paradox on the philosophy of mathematics. By perceiving mathematics as a huge rule-following discipline, one could argue that the Kripkean non-factualist thesis should be adopted within the philosophy of mathematics en bloc to imply a refutation of objectivity and an enforcement of a particular view on the nature of mathematics. In this paper I will discuss this claim. According to Kripke’s skeptical solution we should reject the notion of fact and adopt the use theory of meaning that could be stated as follows: ’One understands the concepts embodied in a language to the extent that one knows how to use the language correctly.’ [Shapiro 1991, 211] [Kripke 1982]. Focusing on mathematical discourse, we should ask: what are the implications of the use theory of meaning for the philosophy of mathematics? Furthermore, is the answer to the skeptical paradox consistent with selected views in philosophy of mathematics? The supposed answer to the first question is that it demands the view that mathematics should be perceived as a strictly pragmatic discipline and the rules of mathematical discourse are mere conventions. But this is too simplistic a view and the matter at hand is far more complicated.

References

Boghossian, P., (1989). The Rule-Following Considerations. Mind, (98(392)).
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCVIII.392.507

Boghossian, P., (1990). The Status of Content. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCIX, No. 2.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2185488

Dummett, M., (1973). Truth and other enigmas. Harvard Univ Press.
View in Google Scholar

Horsten, L., (2012). Philosophy of mathematics. In Zalta, E. N., editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Summer 2012 edition.
View in Google Scholar

Horwich, P., (1998). Meaning. Oxford, Clarendon Press.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/019823824X.001.0001

Kripke, S., (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Harvard Univ Press.
View in Google Scholar

Kusch, M., (2006). A Sceptical Guide to Meaning and Rules: Defending Kripke’s Wittgenstein. Acumen and McGill-Queen’s.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653782

Posłajko, K., (2012). To wszystko nic nie znaczy. Faktualizm i nonfaktualizm w teorii znaczenia. OBI.
View in Google Scholar

Ryle, G., (1951). The Concept of Mind. Hutchinsons University Library.
View in Google Scholar

Shapiro, S., (1991). Foundation without Foundationalism: A Case for Second-order Logic. Clarendon Press.
View in Google Scholar

Shapiro, S. (ed.) (2007). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford University Press.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195325928.001.0001

Tait, W., (2005). The Provenance of Pure Reason. Oxford University Press.
View in Google Scholar

Wilson, G., (1994). Kripke on Wittgenstein on Normativity. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 19 (1994).
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1994.tb00295.x

Wright, C., (1984). Kripke’s Account of the Argument Against Private Language. Journal of Philosophy 71.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2026031

Wright, C., (1993). Realism, Meaning and Truth. Wiley-Blackwell.
View in Google Scholar

Downloads

Published

2016-09-30

How to Cite

Janik, B. (2016). Kripkenstein from the mathematical point of view: a preliminary survey. Hybris, 34(3), 157–170. https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.34.10

Issue

Section

Articles